http://vg06.met.vgwort.de/na/b55a2d7240e548ae800cb245dbc03ec1

Diverse Writings 6

 Critiquing Feenberg on Heidegger's Aristotle and the Question Concerning Technology

Michael Eldred

Back to artefact homepage

artefact text and translation
Cologne, Germany

Last modified 19-Mar-2013
Version 1.0 June 2009
First put on site 12-Jun-2009
Download Sgreek TrueType font (for PC and Mac)

     

    Table of contents

    1. Feenberg's welcome re-reading of Heidegger's lectures and essays on Aristotle 

    2. Narrowing the horizon to technology

     3. Heidegger's critical theses turned affirmative 

      4. The missed connection between movement and time

    5. The still unposed question concerning social power 

    6. The "saving power" and twisting Heidegger free of productivism

     

    1. Feenberg's welcome re-reading of Heidegger's lectures and essays on Aristotle 

    Andrew Feenberg writes in his Heidegger and Marcuse: The Catastrophe and Redemption of History from 2005 as Chapter 2(1) an in-depth review of and critical engagement with Heidegger's interpretations of téchnê in Aristotle and his famous short essay, 'The Question Concerning Technology'. Feenberg rightly notes at the outset that from this essay and his similarly famous 'The Origin of the Work of Art', "one cannot really gauge the depth of Heidegger's analysis of technê nor understand fully how it differs from modern technology" and therefore devotes the chapter to "these issues on the basis of a reading of Heidegger's various lectures and essays on Aristotle", a most promising approach. One obvious option when here taking on Feenberg's chapter would be merely to argue with him over the correct interpretation of Heidegger's various writings on Aristotle with the aim of defending what Heidegger thinks and "believes" about te/xnh and technology, but such an aim would not be particularly fruitful, remaining as it would within the horizon laid out by Heidegger himself. Rather, crucial insights and issues in Heidegger's thinking overlooked by Feenberg's interpretation are to be taken up here and pointed in directions envisaged neither by Feenberg nor by Heidegger himself. 

    Indeed, as one of the best known of today's so-called 'philosophers of technology', Feenberg has already circumscribed an horizon for his thinking, even and especially when pursuing his project of a "democratization of technology"(2) through which he seeks, as the book's title suggests, even a "redemption of history". Hence, when summarizing Heidegger's 'The Question Concerning Technology', Feenberg from the start goes along with Heidegger's equating te/xnh with poi/hsij, i.e. te/xnh with te/xnh poihtikh/ or the technical art of making, even though for the Greeks there is an entire gamut of various te/xnai, a crucial issue I have taken up elsewhere(3) that hangs together with the issue concerning productive power raised below. It is nevertheless to be welcomed that Feenberg 'crosses swords' with Heidegger's thinking on te/xnh and technology because Heidegger himself poses the question concerning technology at the philosophical, i.e. ontological level, where thinking can become crucial and upset all too well-worn paths of thinking, thus disclosing other historical possibilities. 

    Early in the piece, Feenberg raises a qualm: "One is left wondering if Heidegger's thought is based on Aristotle's or if Heidegger merely distorts the Aristotelian texts into a mirror of his own views." How to decide? The phenomena themselves must ultimately decide: Does Heidegger's phenomenological interpretation of Aristotle gell with an account of the simple phenomena, such as making, that are brought before the reader's mind? Heidegger's ground-breaking re-reading of Aristotle's texts in part recovers them insofar as they are true to the phenomena, in part reinterprets them in ways truer to the phenomena, and in part resituates Aristotle's phenomenologically apposite analyses in other contexts. 

    2. Narrowing the horizon to technology 

    A major problem with Feenberg's recounting of Heidegger's interpretations of Aristotle is that Feenberg treats him like himself, namely, as a philosopher of technology. Heidegger's horizon, however, is much wider and his penetration into questions much deeper, so that Feenberg inevitably truncates Heidegger's thinking in recounting it. Heidegger does focus on Plato's and Aristotle's analyses of te/xnh, and learns from them, and, in a certain way and to a certain extent, Sein und Zeit  can be regarded as a translation into German from the ancient Greek right down to the homology between Greek Aristotelean and German Heideggerian terms. Feenberg writes, for instance, "this comportment [Dasein's comportment in the world that "creates an opening" ME] was initially analyzed by the Greeks as technê. Their intuition about the nature of being therefore conformed in its essential structure with Heidegger's Dasein analysis—and vice versa." This ignores that there are subtle shifts in Heidegger's interpretation, quite apart from there being no notion of "opening" or "clearing" in Aristotle, for the existentials applying to Dasein's dealings with equipment are precisely not Aristotelean categories, which is signalled already with the important distinction in the equipment-analysis between Zuhandenheit (being-on-hand) and Vorhandenheit (presence-at-hand). Feenberg is therefore quite wrongheaded to claim with respect to Heidegger's interpretation of te/xnh in Aristotle in terms of "morphê and hyle, eidos, telos, and peras" (where he even confirms unwittingly that "eidos ... appears as present at hand", and not as being-on-hand): "Until the mid 1930s, Heidegger has a primarily positive view of this approach and Being and Time is influenced by it." 

    3. Heidegger's critical theses turned affirmative 

    Where does Feenberg run awry? His false step is to treat Heidegger's early thesis that "Being for the Greeks means having-been-produced (Hergestelltsein)" as a positive thesis which Heidegger himself adopts rather than shakes through questioning. This Heideggerian thesis is coupled with Heidegger's likewise famous early discovery that the tacit, unthought, underlying, unifying meaning of being informing all of Greek thinking on being (which, as we know since Aristotle, is "said in many ways") is precisely "standing presence" (ständige Anwesenheit). (This unifying meaning, of course, is not a genus that is then particularized through drawing in specific differences.) These discoveries are momentous for Heidegger's thinking in far-reaching ways, and they are critical discoveries that allow him to make headway in the deconstruction of Greek metaphysics, and therefore of Western thinking in toto. The critical questioning of Herstellen (pro-ducing, bringing forth into presence), paired with questioning the lo/goj as mode of access to being, leads eventually to the critique of all kinds of thinking that sets up (stellt) and all kinds of setting-up (stellen) in an historical constellation of being Heidegger calls the set-up (Ge-Stell), which in no way can be thought of merely as 'technology'. 

    Heidegger noted in the early 1920s that the tacit sense of being for the Greeks was temporal, namely, presence. Only in this way does Heidegger come to the project of Being and Time, which accurately names the main concern of Heidegger's thinking from beginning to end, even when, in the 1940s, time is designated as the "Vorname" ("preliminary name" GA54:113) for truth, for a)lh/qeia as the clearing of self-concealment. For Heidegger, time does not remain conceived in the Greek, i.e. Aristotelean way, for which only the now properly is, the now (nu=n) that later will become the nunc stans, but rather, time, under Heidegger's hand and with the help of Husserl, becomes precisely three-dimensional, ecstatic, stretched. Such ecstatic time is a feature of Sein und Zeit  and right through to the late, 1962 lecture Zeit und Sein. And the meaning of being itself is then thought from this 3D-time left unthought by the Greeks. By contrast, Aristotle thinks time as the number counted off movement, as clock-time, a conception of time subjected to critique in Being and Time. From within his horizon as technology-philosopher, Feenberg underestimates Heidegger, whose thinking opens a way to rethinking and re-experiencing time and being historically as the clearing of time-space. 

    4. The missed connection between movement and time

    Feenberg also misses the connection between Heidegger's intense focus on Aristotle's ontology of ki/nhsij, on movement and Heidegger's bringing this ontology to shed light on the movement of factical life, i.e. on the movement that is Dasein. Dasein's life-movement is not merely its practical dealings with useful things, but how its taking-care of daily business is embedded in Dasein's self-production of its self, its casting of its self into the temporal ecstasy of the future. Feenberg is therefore right in a way to point out that there are productivist residues in Being and Time, but these concern most essentially Dasein itself in the 'productive' self-casting of its life-movement, an aspect hidden from view to Feenberg with his focus on te/xnh. Heidegger clearly lays before us, especially in 1931 but also earlier,(4) how Aristotle unfolds his ontology of movement and time through his famous triad of concepts, du/namij, e)ne/rgeia and e)ntele/xeia, and Feenberg indeed discusses this triad. However, he confusedly conflates the meaning of the latter two concepts when he glosses the former as "signifying the 'ergon,' or finished work that stands before us in its completion". E)ne/rgeia is literally the at-work-ness of the du/namij or power underway toward to its end, when it will have-itself-in-its-end, the literal meaning of e)ntele/xeia. In other words, e)ne/rgeia is Aristotle's ontological concept for movement itself, signifying a twofold presence of both presence and lack. Because Aristotle takes te/xnh poihtikh/ or the know-how of making as the paradigm for his ontology of movement (covering four kinds of movement), this productivist paradigm enters into the deepest ontological concepts of movement, power and time which then unfold their fateful consequences throughout Western history, in a kind of deep-rooted productivist infection, up to the present day. 

    5. The still unposed question concerning social power

    Heidegger himself must be criticized for preserving, despite modifications, a productivist conception of power, adopted ultimately from Aristotle's analyses of du/namij in the Metaphysics Book Theta. Heidegger never thinks an alternative ontology of power (to wit, as social power) and, of course, this task remains invisible to other philosophers, Feenberg included. For Heidegger, power and making remain tightly bound together, so that, on the one hand, a "step back" is conceived by him as a step back from productive power into the powerlessness of (making preparations for) receiving the dispensations of being, and, on the other, the "saving power" from the set-up is sought in a particular kind of insightful making, namely, the poetic and artistic making of art works.(5) We must pose Heidegger the questions: What has happened to power in his casting of the fourfold (Geviert)? What is the relationship between power and letting-be (Gelassenheit)? Reposing the question concerning power necessarily brings the questions concerning the ontology of movement and time into (re)play. The critique of Heidegger's still productionist conception of power, however, applies also to Feenberg, whose project is that of a democratization of technology that is to give the power over technology to the people without ever posing the ghost of a question concerning the ontology of such a 'power of the people', or democracy. Instead, he wills and wants to become political, and takes conceptions of social and political power for granted — precisely conceptions that are most questionable in their granting and beg philosophical interrogation. It goes without saying — and this is disheartening to note eighty years after Being and Time was first published — that Heidegger's defenders against Feenberg do not see, and show themselves to be stubbornly resistant to seeing, the blind spots in Heidegger's thinking. Who said there's a label on Heidegger reading, 'Do not twist'? 

    6. The "saving power" and twisting Heidegger free of productivism 

    Feenberg has an intense interest in the "saving power", in a redemption from modern technology gone wild and therefore poses in one subsection the question regarding "A Hegelian Heidegger?" who finds "reconciliation" in history. In this way he brings Heidegger into contact with the Marxists, Lukács and Marcuse. "The Hegelian alternative focuses on life as a conflictual process of self-making leading to a harmonious outcome." Note that humankind's "self-making" is a thoroughly productionist conception alloyed with the casting of human being itself as historical subject. Such an "harmonious outcome" would be a reconciliation and an Überwindung (overcoming), in contrast to that Heideggerian figure also cited by Feenberg, namely, Verwindung (getting-over). 

    Verwindung in Heidegger's thinking refers to the possibility of humankind 'getting over' metaphysical thinking that has culminated in the precalculative thinking of the set-up, to make room for another thinking in "the other beginning" (which Feenberg misquotes as "a new beginning"). In the German vernacular, we 'verwinden' or 'get over', for instance, the pain of losing a loved one, who nevertheless remains with us, whereas we 'überwinden' (overcome) obstacles that are thus left behind. When Heidegger asserts that thinking has the lead role to play vis-à-vis art in the transition to the other beginning,(6) he is insisting that the way an historical world opens up is cast first and foremost in philosophical thinking (and not in what Feenberg proposes to name simplifyingly with the nebulous term "culture"), just as the modern age was opened up and cast by a mathematico-scientific, precalculative thinking borne unbeknowns by an unbridled will to productive power over movement inherent in Western philosophy from the first beginning, starting with the motion of physical bodies (Newtonian mechanics) through to all kinds of movement amenable to a quantitative grasping. Verwinden is related to 'winden', to winding and entwining, writhing and twisting. We get over something by twisting free of it. A Verwindung in Western thinking implies a twisting, perhaps subtle, through which an alternative comes into view, through which the world is cast differently from another angle. This alternative cast of being enables also other ways of human acting and living to shape up in the light cast by this alternative. Such an alternative only becomes possible when all the cards are on the table, that is, when all the deepest ontological issues have been raised and thought through. From this perspective, Heidegger is not a final word; rather, the blind spots in his momentous thinking leave us with questions that in no way can be confined to a philosophy of technology. The question concerning power, comprising both productive power and the power play of social interplay, remains open after Heidegger. 


      Notes
      1. Available as 'The Question Concerning Technê: Heidegger's Aristotle' downloaded on 06-Jun-2009. Chapter 2 of Heidegger and Marcuse: The Catastrophe and Redemption of History Routledge, 2005, 176 pp. Back to 1

      2.  
      3. Cf. Feenberg's books Critical Theory of Technology (1991), Alternative Modernity (1995), Questioning Technology (1999) and the collection of essays Democratizing Technology: Andrew Feenberg's Critical Theory of Technology ed. Tyler J. Veak, SUNY Press 2006. Back to 2

      4.  
      5. See my 'Technology, Technique, Interplay: Questioning Die Frage nach der Technik', a paper presented to the School of Philosophy at the University of Sydney on 10 September 2008, the 41st Annual North American Heidegger Conference 03-05 May 2007 at DePaul University in Chicago and (in an earlier version) to the conference 4. Aussprache über die Philosophie Martin Heideggers 01-03 June 2006 at the Bergische University in Wuppertal, Germany. Back to 3

      6.  
      7. Cf. M. Heidegger Grundbegriffe der aristotelischen Philosophie Marburger Vorlesung SS 1924 Gesamtausgabe Band 18, ed. Mark Michalski 2002 § 26. Bewegung als e)ntelexei/a tou= duna/mei o)/ntoj (Phys. G 1) et seq., Platon: Sophistes Marburger Vorlesung WS 1924/25 Gesamtausgabe Band 19 ed. Ingeborg Schüßler 1992 GA19:100ff, Die Grundbegriffe der antiken Philosophie Marburger Vorlesung SS 1926 Gesamtausgabe Band 22, ed. Franz-Karl Blust, Viertes Kapital Das Problem der Bewegung und seine ontologische Bedeutung. Ursprung, Sinn und Funktion von du/namij und e)ne/rgeia §§ 61-64 GA22:170ff, Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie Marburger Vorlesung SS 1927 Gesamtausgabe Band 24 ed. F-W. v. Herrmann 1975 § 19 a) b) Auslegung des Aristotelischen Zeitbegriffs GA24:336ff, and finally Aristoteles, Metaphysik Theta 1-3: Von Wesen und Wirklichkeit der Kraft Freiburger Vorlesung SS 1931 Gesamtausgabe Band 33 ed. Heinrich Hüni 1981. Back to 4

      8.  
      9. For more depth and extension on the critique of Heidegger's restricted ontological conception of power, see 'Assessing How Heidegger Thinks Power Through the History of Being', 'Heidegger's Restricted Interpretation of the Greek Conception of the Political', Social Ontology Recasting Political Philosophy Through a Phenomenology of Whoness ontos verlag, Frankfurt, 2008 esp. Chapters 5 and 10, and The Digital Cast of Being: Metaphysics, Mathematics, Cartesianism, Cybernetics, Capitalism, Communication ontos verlag, Frankfurt 2009. Back to 5

      10.  
      11. Cf. e.g. "Not poetry goes first, but in the transition the trail-blazer must be thinking. In future, however, art is the setting-into-the-work of truth (or it no longer exists at all) — one essential grounding of the essencing of truth." (Nicht die Dichtung ist das erste, sondern Wegbereiter muß im Übergang das Denken sein. Die Kunst aber ist künftig — oder sie ist gar nicht mehr — das Ins-Werk-setzen der Wahrheit — eine wesentliche Gründung des Wesens der Wahrheit. M. Heidegger Grundfragen der Philosophie: Ausgewählte 'Probleme' der 'Logik' Freiburger Vorlesung WS 1937/38 Gesamtausgabe Band 45 ed. F.-W. von Herrmann 1984 GA45:190 italics in the original). Back to 6

      12.  
      13. Back to 7

      14.  


      Copyright (c) 2009 by Michael Eldred, all rights reserved. This text may be used and shared in accordance with the fair-use provisions of U.S. and international copyright law, and it may be archived and redistributed in electronic form, provided that the author is notified and no fee is charged for access. Archiving, redistribution, or republication of this text on other terms, in any medium, requires the consent of the author.

      Back to artefact homepage
      artefact